Zombies Dolphins and Blindsight

Dolphin

Is consciousness the hardest of hard problems? Is it all down to bits of wiring in the brain or quantum mechanics? And do animals know more than we think?

Alun Anderson, Bob Holmes and Liz Else.

What's the definition of a scientist? Someone who looks for a black cat in a dark room. And a philosopher? Someone who looks for a black cat in a dark room where there is no black cat.
By sheer coincidence, this drollery appeared in the horoscope section of the Tucson Weekly newspaper just as 800 scientists and philosophers gathered for the second biennial Tucson conference, "Towards a Science of Consciousness". The cat the scientists are looking for is an explanation of how processes in the brain create conscious awareness. They haven't captured their cat yet but occasional sightings make them believe they will one day.
[I wonder if this elusive cat is the younger cousin of the elusive lion in physics? -LB]

Black Cat

Whether the cat the philosophers are after-the so-called "hard problem" of consciousness exists at all is much more in doubt. If it does, the scientists are in deep trouble. Salvos between them and the believers in the hard problem dominated the opening day and reverberated throughout the conference. Whoever is right, one thing is certain - consciousness remains the first and last of the great human mysteries.

So what kind of problem is it? The philosophers of the hard school think that consciousness is in a league of its own. Consciousness, they argue, has absolutely unique properties: it is private, subjective, peculiar to the individual, and cannot be directly observed by a third person.
As David Chalmers of the University of California, Santa Cruz, and the hardest of the hard school of philosophers, summed it up after the last Tucson conference: "When we see, we experience visual sensations-the felt quality of redness, the experience of dark and light, the quality of depth in a visual field. Other experiences go along with perception in different modalities-the sound of a clarinet, the smell of mothballs... Then there are bodily sensations from pains to orgasms - mental images that are conjured up internally, the felt quality of emotion, and the experience of a stream of conscious thought. What unites all of these states is that there is something it is to be to be in them. All of them are states of experience."

The hard school believes that understanding how the brain works does not automatically mean we will understand consciousness. They accept that we will be able, for example, to trace the visual processes that help us to discriminate colour, starting with cells in the retina that respond to different wavelengths of light. But really explaining consciousness, explaining why these neural processes should be accompanied by a feeling of "what it is like to be me", is a completely different kind of problem, says Chalmers.

Indeed, he has suggested that consciousness might turn out to be an irreducible property, in the same category as time and space, and understanding it may force us to rewrite everything we know abut the Universe. Others think that consciousness can be explained only by turning to a field such as quantum mechanics, where normal laws of causality seem not to hold.

This is all nonsense for those on the other side. At Tucson, Daniel Dennett, from Tufts University, author of Consciousness Explained was first to attack. Facing an audience mostly sympathetic to the hard problem stance, Dennett said he felt like "a cop at Woodstock". But this didn't stop him from absolutely dismissing the hard problem.
For Dennett, there is no mysterious process required for the brain's information processing capabilities to become "conscious": the brain is a kind of hypothesis-making machine, constantly throwing up new "drafts" of what is going on in the world.

"Mental states," explains Dennett, "do not become conscious by entering some special chamber in the brain, nor by being transduced into some privileged and mysterious medium but by winning the competition against other mental states for domination in the control of behaviour." Those who think that brain processes cannot explain our first-person experience of consciousness have the question all wrong, according to Dennett. "It presupposes that what you are is something else-in addition to all of this brain-body activity. But what you are, however just is the organisation of all this competitive activity between this host of competencies which your body has developed. You automatically know about these things going on inside your body because if you didn't, it wouldn't be your body."

Later in the week, Patricia Churchland from the Institute for Neural Computation at La Jolla, California, weighed in with Dennett. Setting conscious experience on a pedestal as the hard problem may be counterproductive, she said.
"It suggests that we can already see that the hard problem is going to have to have a real humdinger of a solution-that it's going to have to be really radical, that it's going to have to come from somewhere really neat like quantum mechanics, that it can't just be a matter of a complex, dynamical system doing its thing. Well, I can't actually see that," concluded Churchland.

'Mental states become conscious by winning the competition against other mental states...'


Language gives us our clearest view into the consciousness of other people through our myriad social dealings.
Some researchers have tried to peek through the same window into the minds of other species, and many have come away with the distinct feeling that these other animals may also be conscious. This viewpoint used to attract scorn, but recently the evidence has become much stronger that humans are not alone in using language and in forming abstract concepts.

"The mind of the ape cannot be that much different from our own," says Sue Savage- Rumbaugh from Georgia State University, who is one of the most passionate believers that apes, at least, have a well-developed consciousness.
The first attempts to teach an ape to "speak"-in sign language, since apes lack the vocal apparatus to speak aloud-proved disappointing, she admits. A female chimp named Washoe was never good enough at communicating to convince sceptics that she was actively using language.

But Washoe was only taught to speak, not to listen-a crucial omission, says Savage- Rumbaugh. She taught a pair of chimps called Sherman and Austin together and their language abilities burgeoned as they learnt to listen to one another and used language to cooperate to their mutual benefit.
More recently, Savage-Rumbaugh reared a pair of bonobos, or pygmy chimpanzees, in the company of humans who spoke English to them and pointed to symbols on a board. While the bonobos, Kanzi,and Panbanisha, never received any explicit training in language, they picked it up anyway.

"These conditions are all that is needed for apes to acquire understanding of language at least equal to a three-year-old child," says Savage-Rumbaugh. For example, the bonobos can respond correctly, even on first hearing, to new sentences such as "Can you find the pine needles in the refrigerator?"
Kanzi and Panbanisha clearly understand even more complex concepts, says Savage- Rumbaugh, for example, Panbanisha watched as a human secretly substituted a bug for some sweets in a box. When a second human tried to open the box, the first human asked the bonobo "What is she looking for?" Panbanisha replied that the human was looking for the sweets. "To answer a question as sophisticated as this, Panbanisha needs a concept of what thinking is, and that other people's thinking is different from her own, says Savage-Rumbaugh.
[Psychological experiments with children show that they don't have a concept of what is in the mind of someone else until about the age of three.These animals then, are out-thinking a three year old human -LB]

Even more strikingly, Panbanisha added that the first person was being "bad" to play such a trick-the same comment that the researcher's four-year-old daughter made.
[Oddly showing moral judgement,this may come as a surprise to those that do not credit animals with intelligence -LB]
Wild bonobos that have never been exposed to human language may also use language of a sort to communicate with one another. Bonobos hang out in the treetops in large groups of between 60 and 100 individuals, but when they move from roost to roost they travel across the ground in smaller groups.

On a recent trip to Zaire, Savage-Rumbaugh noticed that bonobos had carefully broken off plants of the same species just before and after two trails crossed,apparently as a way of marking which fork to take for the groups following them. Intrigued, she began to search the forest for more markings. She found 96 places where plants had clearly been broken off by bonobos. All but a handful served as some sort of trail-marking.
Apes undoubtedly show the clearest evidence of conscious thought among nonhuman animals. Similar intelligence might be much harder to recognise in, say, dolphins, simply because they are so different from us. Humans and some apes use their hands to fashion tools, a sign of intelligence. "How do we look for intelligence in a non-handed animal?" asks Diana Reiss of Rutgers University in New Jersey.

On land, humans know that trail-marking is clever, but what takes its place in the ocean? Humans can talk to apes, and the apes can sign back, but how could we communicate with a dolphin?
Despite these difficulties, Reiss sees clear glimpses of an active intelligence. "I often walk away thinking there's somebody in there - or maybe I should say, there's some mind in there," says Reiss.
For example, the dolphins she studies at Marine World Africa in Vallejo, California, blow bubble rings, just as humans blow smoke rings from cigarettes, and then play with the rings as they rise to the surface.

She has even seen them drop various items, such as bits of fish or seaweed, into the centre of a bubble ring and watch how the turbulence buffets them. "It looks like intelligent, goal-directed behaviour," she says. "I felt like I was watching a bunch of scientists testing contingencies."
If researchers have a hard time measuring intelligence in a dolphin, they find it still harder to crawl inside the brain of a bird. Yet here, too, at least one researcher sees glimmerings of what may be consciousness. For twenty years, Irene Pepperberg of the University of Arizona has studied the mental capacities of a grey parrot called Alex , who listens to questions in English and responds aloud with English words.

** BLOG - SCIAM OBSERVATIONS ** An interview with Alex, the African grey parrot
As you may have heard, Alex, the celebrated African Grey parrot, died recently. In 1996, former Scientific American editor Madhusree Mukerjee paid Alex a visit at Pepperberg's lab, then at the University of Arizona.
[Scientific American 2007]

'I often walk away thinking there's somebody in there' or maybe I should say, there's some mind in there'

"Alex is no Einstein. We think he's an average parrot," says Pepperberg. Nevertheless, Alex can count objects up to six, recognise shapes and colours, and perform simple comparisons such as same/different and larger/smaller. Alex can also ask for objects, and he will correct his trainer if she gives the wrong response. If Alex says "wanna grape", for example, and is given a piece of banana instead, about three times out of four he will say "no", then repeat his request. Pepperberg won't go so far as to claim that this behaviour shows that Alex can consciously compare his expectations to reality, but she does believe that "there's certainly a 'there' there".

What kind of a "there" might it be? It's tempting to see consciousness as an all or nothing phenomenon but that's a mistake. A parrot may be conscious of what is going on around it but, to paraphrase Dennett, it probably can't wonder whether it's Friday and even whether it's a parrot.
If anyone can be considered the grandfather of the hard problem school of consciousness it is Rene Descartes, born 400 years ago this year. His meditations on the unique unity of consciousness, which convinced him that "mind" and "body" were separate, were quoted at length at Tucson by Michael Lockwood, from Green College, Oxford.

"When I consider the mind," wrote Descartes, "that is myself in so far as am merely a conscious being. I can distinguish no part within myself. I understand myself to be a single and complete thing. Nor can the faculties of feeling, will, understanding and so on be called its parts, for it is one and the same mind that wills, feels and understands."

Descartes may have thought his consciousness was a unity, but neurologists today would not agree. There is, they say, no more graphic evidence of the way consciousness is "assembled" from different neuronal processes than the bizarre way that brain injuries can tear them apart.
Perhaps most startling of all is "blindsight",which violates our common-sense view of consciousness. Here, damage to areas of the primary visual cortex removes all sensation of light or colour from corresponding areas of the visual field. Patients with this damage appear totally blind in one part of the visual field. If asked whether they can see an object in this area, the answer obviously enough, is no.

But, astonishingly, if the patients are forced to guess where this object they cannot see is located, they often point at it quite accurately. Although they have lost all conscious sensation of "seeing", at some level they are still able to see. "Consciousness" and the brain's information processing thus appear split.
What can it be like to have blindsight? Most patients simply say they are totally blind and cannot understand why experimenters ask them to "guess" where objects are when it is obviously pointless. But Larry Weiskrantz from the University of Oxford, who coined the term blindsight, has described how a few can have a mysterious feeling of awareness under the right circumstances. "It's a sense that I haven't got, if that makes sense," was how one patient explained it.

Blindsight is possible, the neurologists assume, because the visual pathway splits into many parallel streams as it approaches the cortex and some streams go on to different parts of the brain, bypassing the primary visual cortex. Although these parts of the brain cannot create visual consciousness, they can provide some unconscious information to guide behaviour. Blindsight can thus give clues as to which parts of the brain are essential to generate consciousness.
Damage even higher in the visual system or in the prefrontal cortex - where the planning of behaviour takes place and links to motor output are made - creates even more bizarre problems. Lesions may not so much remove consciousness as strip away some of its attributes.

The conscious vision of patients with damage in the extrastriate cortex may lack one or more qualities: the patients can "see" but they may not be able to detect colour or movement. In philosophers' jargon, they have lost one or more of the "qualia" which populate the conscious sensory world.
Some damage within the extrastriate cortex may leave the patient able to sense a full repertoire of qualia but destroy the ability to bind them together to perceive a whole object. This is called aperceptive agnosia.

"Such patients," says Petra Stoerig from the Institute of Medical Psychology in Munich, "may have normal visual fields, normal acuity, normal brightness discrimination, normal colour vision, normal motion processing, but still they are unable to form an object out of these impressions." If they are shown a triangle, for example, they can see it but they cannot connect it with other geometric objects such as a circle or a square. If they try to make drawings of objects, they can produce only meaningless scribbles.

Defects elsewhere in the extrastriate cortex can rob consciousness of more of its normal qualities. To recognise, as well as see, an object, you must be able to create a web of associations around it by naming it and recalling things about it. These processes are destroyed in patients suffering from associative agnosia. They can see objects and make drawings of them perfectly well, but they cannot recognise the objects, nor say what they do, explains Stoerig.

Even stranger is the world of people suffering from anosognosia. The condition occasionally occurs after stroke damage to the right side of the brain which leaves the patient paralysed on the left side of the body. Despite their obvious paralysis, however, anosognosics claim that their useless limbs work perfectly well.
"This has got to be the most peculiar thing I've ever seen in all of neurology," says Vilayanur Ramachandran [Ref: Iotm11], of the University of California, San Diego who described his work with such patients to the conference. "Here is somebody perfectly sane and rational, who watches her arm not performing and yet claims she is not paralysed."

When Ramachandran asked one patient to touch him on the nose, for example, she insisted that she was doing so, even though her arm remained limp at her side. When he asked her to clap, she beat the air with her good arm but said she was clapping normally.
Another after failing repeatedly to tie her shoe, insisted she had in fact tied it "with both hands" - a point that normal individuals rarely bother to mention. This is evidence that deep down, anosognosics may know the truth.
If this were a purely psychological delusion, it should apply equally to left and right-side paralysis. But anosognosia shows up almost exclusively in people with paralysis on the left side. This suggests that there must be specific neurological damage to the right side of the brain, says Ramachandran.

Anosognosia is a problem of the mind's belief system, not its perceptual system, Ramachandran thinks.The mind needs a theory of the world in order to organise and make sense of the constant stream of sensory inputs. But the theory - making part of the brain must also be able to ignore inputs that don't fit with its world view, lest every mistaken perception shake us to our roots. In Ramachandran's hypothesis, this bull-headed theorist resides in the left half of the brain.
The right half of the brain, he thinks, acts as devil's advocate. When too much conflicting data accumulates-for example, repeated awareness that the left arm cannot move-the devil's advocate overcomes the left brain's defence mechanisms and forces it to restructure its world view to fit the new information.

He thinks that in people with anosognosia "that mechanism - your devil's advocate - is damaged, and the left brain is free to pursue a strategy of denial and confabulation. There is no limit to the delusion."

'Their first goal, hard problem or no hard problem, is to find a neural correlate of consciousness'

No longer need one spend time attempting to understand the far-fetched speculations of physicists, nor endure the tedium of philosophers perpetually disagreeing with each other. Consciousness is now largely a scientific problem."
For those who think that neurobiology will provide the answers and the hard problem is a philosopher's delusion, this fighting talk from Nobel laureate Francis Crick is just what is needed. His words, taken from an article published two months earlier in Nature, were quoted approvingly by the neurobiologists at Tucson. And although Crick was not at the conference, his long-term collaborator, Christof Koch, of the California Institute of Technology, was there to lay out the game plan.

Their first goal, hard problem or no hard problem, is to find a "neural correlate of consciousness"-activities in the brain that correspond specifically to the workings of conscious awareness.
The search begins by locating areas where changing neural activity can be specifically linked to changing awareness of phenomena. To find these areas, neurobiologists are making use of cunning experiments in which stimuli from the external world hold constant while awareness changes - either spontaneously or as a result of conscious activity.

Vase illusion

Long-established work on illusions provides the most fertile hunting ground for such effects. When we look at the famous "vase" illusion, after a little while, we alternately see the vase and two faces. The stimulus does not change but what we see in mind's eye does.
The most complete experiments of this sort came from Nikos Logothetis of Baylor College of Medicine at Houston. "Like Crick and Koch, we wondered if there were any neurons that are specifically related to the act of perceiving," said Logothetis. His experiments on monkeys used visual illusions that can be generated by a phenomenon called binocular rivalry.

In Logothetis's first experiments, a set of stripes slanting one way was shown to one eye and an identical set slanting in the opposite direction was shown to the other eye. After a short while, the two alternate irregularly -just like the vase and the two faces-as the incompatible inputs from the two eyes battle with each other: the stimuli do not change but what the monkey "sees" does.
Logothetis trained his monkeys to press a bar according to which way the stripes appeared to be oriented. At the same time, he made electrical recordings from numerous places at different levels along the visual pathways. The firing pattern of many cells remained constant whatever the monkey reported seeing- the neurons were locked into the unchanging stimuli presented to each eye. But the behaviour of some neurons correlated very closely with the monkey's awareness. Their firing pattern changed dramatically just before the monkey switched bars to report that the lines were changing from one orientation to another.

Many of these neurons were found in an area known as V4, at the top of the hierarchy of the visual cortex. This location fits well with the view of consciousness put forward by Crick and Koch. They believe that you cannot be consciously aware of the information processing that goes on in the lower parts of the visual system, from the retina up to the primary visual cortex called V1. Consciousness is related to the high-level, "explicit", representations generated at the top of the visual cortex.
An explicit representation is seen in cells that respond only to a complex property of an object, rather than to dots or lines or patches of brightness. The best known of the "explicit" neurons are those found in the mid-temporal cortex that respond only to faces seen from a particular angle. Damage to this area causes prosopagnosia, an inability to recognise familiar faces.

To generate a full conscious experience, Crick and Koch postulate that cells which code explicitly for a face, for example, must somehow link up to many other neurons that relate to them-perhaps to the name of the person, memories involving the person and so on. They must also link to the motor cortex so that the experience can generate a response.
How all this happens is anyone's guess right now, but we would expect consciousness to arise in neurons linking the highest parts of the visual system with the prefrontal cortex which contains the language centres and areas involved in planning action.

Sue Greenfield Not everyone wants to see the "hard problem" solved. Unlike the so-called "easy problems" - explaining how the brain carries out its various information processing tasks from analysing the colour of objects to processing a stream of words-solving the hard problem means understanding phenomenal consciousness.
Susan Greenfield of the University of Oxford  [Ref: Iotm11] described a theory by which the fleeting recruitment of populations of neurons could be linked to the level of consciousness. But the theory would not necessarily grasp how it feels to be a specific individual with a unique, private view of the world. All anyone would be able to point to, she said, was an increasingly refined correlation between the behaviour of a group of neurons and some measure of consciousness. That would not solve the hard problem.
Greenfield was happy with that. "If we really and deeply knew how groups of neurons generated consciousness, then we couldn't exclude the possibility that we could hack into each other's consciousness," she said."If we did that, then we'd annihilate the individual, and I for one would not want to see that day."

As Koch explains: "Naively put, neurons in the visual part of the brain project forwards to the prefrontal [cortex], and the prefrontal looks back at the high-level visual output. That interaction is where we believe the neural correlate of consciousness arises."
At Tucson, Logothetis reported new binocular rivalry experiments with monkeys pitting pictures of faces against pictures of objects while recording from face recognition neurons. Once again, he found some cells that started firing just before the monkey pulled a lever to say it was now seeing a face.

But when he was asked if he thought he had found possible candidates for the neural correlate of consciousness, Logothetis was cautious: "When there is a pattern that is consistently happening somewhere, you still don't know if it is a cause or an effect."
Finding neurons that appear to track visual awareness is still just the first step to pinning down the neural correlate of consciousness. The key step now is to find out what these neurons are connected to and how they respond.

At least the hunt has begun and more results can be expected as researchers turn to humans. Excitement was high at the possibilities offered by functional magnetic resonance imaging -the most sophisticated of all of the new brain scanners.
Roger Tootell of the Massachusetts General Hospital's Nuclear Magnetic Resonance Center is one of the pioneers with his work using the waterfall illusion: if you stare at a waterfall or anything moving continuously and then look away, stationary objects seem to stream by in the opposite direction. Using a brain scanner to study subjects while they experienced the illusion, Tootell was able to map the parts of the brain that changed as the perception faded away. Once again, parts of the mid-temporal cortex appeared critical.

The real fun will come when these imaging techniques are applied in cases where visual awareness has been split off from information processing in the brain. Weiskrantz has already experimented with one of his blindsight subjects who develops some degree of "awareness" of the stimulus if it has enough contrast. His experiments were designed to see what changes in the brain as the subject shifts between the "aware" state and the "unaware" state. Results are expected any day.
"As far as consciousness is concerned, one is in a powerful position if one can compare aware and unaware modes," says Weiskrantz. "We may be able to sneak up on the process of the neural basis of awareness."

There's just one small snag, however: blindsight patients are hard to find. Instead, researchers may be able to turn to "induced blindsight". Late last year, Christopher Kolb and Jochen Braun from Koch's group at Caltech reported an experiment like that described in the figure below. Such displays, "too terrible to behold" as Braun described them, leaves people able to use vision while removing conscious awareness of what they are "seeing".

Roger Penrose
Roger Penrose: toiling at the quantum face

The patterns appear to interfere with visual processing in the primary visual cortex in much the same way at lesions in this region interfere with processing in people with true blindsight. These experiments will make it possible to use MRI to study neural changes as the brain shifts between consciously "aware" and "unaware" states.
Even "hard man" Chalmers was impressed by the new possibilities. Induced blindsight work is most promising since it deals with normal subjects. That's going to explode in the next few years," he predicts.

Koch's own vision of the future of neurobiology was even more euphoric. If, as he thinks, there are very specific neurons that have to be activated to encode the specific content of visual awareness, then they must have something unique about them.
"If that is true, then by definition there has to be a set of genes that codes for them and that means that at some point you'll be able to get an antibody or set of antibodies for the neurons that are your correlate of visual awareness. This will then let you use the power of molecular biology to make incredible progress. You can then stain these neurons, you can maybe transiently inactivate them and see what happens." It might even be possible to create a "zombie", a creature that has everything but awareness, thereby showing by default just what consciousness gives us.

Two big ideas emerged at the first Tucson conference in 1994 that have caused a stir in the consciousness community ever since: one was the "hard problem". as championed by Chalmers, which is very much alive.
The other is the brainchild of Roger Penrose, a mathematician from Oxford University [Ref: Iotm49], and anaesthesiologist Stuart Hameroff of the university of Arizona. Consciousness, they claim, arises from quantum-mechanical processes taking place within tubes of protein inside nerve cells (see "Quantum states of mind", New Scientist, 20 August 1994, p35).

Visual Illusion

It's easy to see in each of these two images that there is a small square (here towards the upper left corner) which stands out because it contains short lines running at right angles to those in the surroundings. But if the two images are shown simultaneously to the right and left eye for a very short time the square vanishes. The images appear to fuse in the brain: adding them together will obviously superimpose a line slanting to the left on every line slanting to the right so that no overall area of discrepancy remains. The square cannot now be seen but if it is moved from one corner of the figure to another,subjects can still reliably report where it is. They can thus "see" the square but cannot consciously perceive it-the phenomenon of induced blindsight.

On the face of it, quantum mechanics is tremendously seductive. Quantum processes operate without cause and effect, a very appealing notion since it leaves room for free will and spontaneity.
Penrose also argues that human minds do things that networks of nerve cells and the computers modelled on them can never do: "understanding is a quality, I claim, that cannot be captured in any form of computation whatever." The unpredictability of quantum events provides a noncomputable way for understanding to arise in the brain, he argues.
Despite their appeal, however, quantum processes take place at atomic or subatomic scales and in the merest whisper of a microsecond-far too small and fast, seemingly, to affect nerve cells.

But at the first Tucson conference, Penrose and Hameroff proposed that microtubules- cylindrical tubes of protein molecules called tubulin, which form the internal skeleton of cells- might provide a safe haven in which quantum events could multiply until they became powerful enough to make a difference.
What are these events? Quantum theory maintains that an electron, for example, has no location at any particular time until some later event requires it to have one. Until then, the electron could be anywhere, and its position is described by a probability function.

Similarly, the outcome of any event at the quantum level is not determined until some later event demands it. In a new twist, Penrose and Hameroff suggested that vast armies of tubulin molecules may suddenly and spontaneously resolve their quantum uncertainties. Each time this happens, we have an experience, they said.
The audience was somewhat less than overwhelmed, however, and a show of hands indicated that most of them remained sceptical, in large part, because no one has found any experimental evidence that anything like this is actually going on.

"If we're going to see the quantum approach flower, what we need is not just a matching of equations. What we need is some good experimental evidence." says Churchland, who is one of the tartest critics of what she calls "Penrose's toilings".
Moreover. says Churchland, "even if the theory is true, how does that explain the phenomenon at issue? I haven't seen the slightest explanation of what all that might have to do with consciousness."
Of course, that's pretty much what Chalmers says about the neuroscientists...
| Problem of Consciousness | Brain Tour | Machinery and Intelligence | Alan Turing | Amanda Sharkey | New Scientist : Read My Mind


Further Reading

The Emperor's New Mind Roger Penrose
Shadows of the Mind Roger Penrose
Consciousness Explained Daniel Dennett
Brainpower Susan Greenfield (Editor) Element Books Ltd
The Human Brain Susan Greenfield Published 1998 Phoenix Press Paperback
The Human Mind Explained Susan Greenfield Published 1998 Ward Lock Paperback
Ultimate Computing: Biomolecular Consciousness and NanoTechnology Stuart Hameroff

MAIN INDEX

REFERENCE GUIDE

TRANSCRIPTS

GLOSSARY

Chaos Quantum Logic Cosmos Conscious Belief Elect. Art Chem. Maths


New Scientist 4 May 1996 File Info: Created 23/7/2000 Updated 19/9/2007 Page Address: http://members.fortunecity.com/templarser/zombie.html